{Pascal the existential Russian blue cat here continues, and possibly concludes, his excursus on the modern political expropriation of the Pauline ‘Katechon,’ an expropriation associated primarily with the Nazi legal theorist Carl Schmitt.}
“The task of understanding history is knowing what the Katechon is and what it isn’t.” (Paul Krause)
As Wikipedia forthrightly states, “Carl Schmitt (11 July 1888 – 7 April 1985) was a German jurist, political theorist, geopolitician, and prominent member of the Nazi Party.” We will not belabor Carl Schmitt’s association with the Nazi regime, an association he never renounced and for which he never apologized; instead, we will consider his ideas on their own merit, the idea under consideration at the moment being that of the Katechon, a mysterious (if not mythical) beast referred to in Paul’s second letter to his congregation in Thessalonica. 1
It would be difficult to find a stronger advocate for the Katechon than Carl Schmitt, who wrote (in his postwar book, The Nomos of the Earth), "I believe in the Katechon: it is for me the only possible way to understand Christian history and to find it meaningful." Schmitt claimed that post-Constantinian Christianity, at least until the Reformation, assumed the Katechonic role previously assigned to imperial Rome, that of keeping chaos at bay and allowing history to continue. “Empire,” said Schmitt, “meant the historical power to restrain the appearance of the Antichrist and the end of the present eon,” and what was Christendom but empire by another name? Schmitt explained:
The unity of [Christendom] was its adequate succession of order in empire and priesthood; it had its visible agents in emperor and pope. The attachment to Rome signified a continuation of ancient orientations adopted by the Christian faith. The history of the Middle Ages is thus the history of a struggle for, and not against, Rome. The continuity that bound medieval international law to the Roman Empire was found not in norms and general ideas, but in the concrete orientation to Rome. This Christian empire was not eternal. It always had its own end and that of the present eon in view. Nevertheless, it was capable of being a historical power. The decisive historical concept of this continuity was that of the restrainer: katechon.
Following Germany’s humiliating surrender in 1919, with harsh, punitive terms imposed by the Allies, Schmitt, then in his early thirties, observed the resultant breakdown of order—political, economic, social, and cultural. In the ensuing years, the decadence of the Weimar Republic shocked him; worse, the political impotence of the postwar German state presented, to Schmitt, the very real possibility of complete national disintegration. Such a fate was intolerable, and, when Hitler’s National Socialist Party maneuvered its way into power, Schmitt believed that Nazism, whatever its shortcomings, restored order and prosperity, bringing Germany not just respect but prestige.
But if, in Schmitt’s view, Adolf Hitler served as a Katechon for Germany, he and his regime quickly became a force for global chaos; at which point, Schmitt, seeing his country and the world embroiled in what seemed to be an apocalyptic conflict, began to view the forces allied against Germany as katechonic themselves. After World War II, with the militant, atheist Soviet Union looming on the horizon (and controlling half of German territory), the anti-communist Schmitt, having spent a year in an Allied internment camp, publicly embraced both American military power and America’s policy of nuclear deterrence; to save the world from godlessness and chaos, it seemed the Katechon might have to destroy it.
From the beginning, Schmitt’s political theories were rooted in fear of disorder. Ironically, his conception of politics as a way of playing out enmity between social groups (as opposed to reconciling such groups) leads inevitably to disorder. Carl Raschke called Schmitt’s theories “a kind of friend-enemy hyperbolicism” in which politics is simply war by other means. Since all is fair in love and war, the political enemy can be (must be) vilified and demonized; politics thus becomes a realm of lawlessness, the very thing Schmitt wanted the State to protect against. Schmitt did not shy away from the logical conclusion; such political failure required the ascension to power of a dictator, someone who would suspend the normal rules of politics (and of representative government) to set things right and to restore order.
To be sure, Schmitt accepted the need for authoritarian rule only under (undefined) exigent circumstances. “Schmitt argued,” says M. Blake Wilson, that, since “no collection of posited laws can foreshadow the vicissitudes of political engagement, liberals must reconcile themselves with the necessity of dictatorship intended to save the constitution from its enemies. Accordingly, Schmitt claimed, a liberal political theory which fails to acknowledge the possibility of dictatorship fatally ignores political reality, which demands that liberal values must be set aside [at times] to preserve the constitution.”
Moreover, Wilson continues, “Schmitt argued that liberalism fails as a political doctrine because of its inability to countenance a leader who faces the possibility of having to make necessary yet anti-liberal decisions when the very existence of the nation requires it to act decisively.” It is never clear who decides that the nation’s existence is threatened, or how the polis can distinguish between a genuine national existential crisis and a manufactured one.
Perhaps Schmitt would have said that such concerns were secondary; the important thing was that the State—or someone wielding its power—had to be strong enough, and resolute enough, to do what needed to be done. In the words of Paul Krause, “The State as Katechon was Schmitt’s secular god; the State embodies all the characteristics and attributes of God. It is the State that literally saves us from killing one another and living miserable lives in the state of nature.” Schmitt believed that the modern liberal State lacked the determination to preserve itself at all costs from enemies both foreign and domestic; he worried that the modern West would not rise to the occasion when a Katechon was required to prevent the triumph of evil.
Were Schmitt’s forebodings correct, and was his willingness to abandon the liberal constitutional order justified? Is the Katechon, whoever or whatever it is, our only hope? Paul, who invented the Katechon, presumably saw it as providing merely a temporary reprieve before (a) all Hell would break loose and (b) Jesus would return to take out the trash, as it were. What part of the Parousia did Carl Schmitt not welcome? In any case, his service to Nazi Germany helped bring humanity to the brink of Armageddon, the very thing he claimed to dread, which is to say, I would not put a lot of stock in his theories.
-------------------------------------------------------------------
1 Carl Schmitt - Wikipedia As usual, the Wikipedia entry has its critics. For those interested in Schmitt’s thought, Gopal Balakrishnan’s The Enemy (published in 2000) testifies to the resurgence of interest in the topic.
Recent Comments